The Collected Works of Samuel Alexander
Introduction
Samuel Alexander is one of the most revered figures in
the history of British philosophy. Everyone who has written about
him from personal knowledge has presented us with a man of many
virtues and almost no faults, and the faults that have been recorded
are of the harmless variety, such as an indifference to dress and
personal appearance. His favourite form of locomotion was a bicycle,
and he was known to ride great distances - from Manchester to
Liverpool, say - to keep appointments. Once, so the story goes, he
arrived, after a long bicycle trip during which he was caught in a
storm, wet and muddy at the home of friends who had invited him to
dinner. When the maid answered his knock, he asked if he might have
a bath. Since he looked every inch a tramp, the maid curtly turned
him down and shut him out. Only after he knocked again and explained
who he was, was he admitted. His students and his colleagues in
Manchester University, where he spent most of his career, were
prepared to overlook such matters as his dress, because he was such
an important asset to the university. A superb teacher and an
untiring colleague, Alexander contributed greatly to the
transformation of Owens College into the University of Manchester.
The University honoured him by commissioning Jacob Epstein to sculpt
a bust of him, which is still prominently displayed there. After
Epstein had completed the bust, Alexander wrote an article, 'The
Creative Process in the Artist's Mind',1 describing what
it was like to sit for him. In 1930 Alexander was honoured by King
George V with induction into the Order of Merit, a very select
society limited to twenty-four living persons. Other philosophers
who have shared this honour are Isaiah Berlin, G.E. Moore, Bertrand
Russell and Alfred North Whitehead.
Samuel Alexander was born in Sydney, Australia, on 6
January 1859. His father having died before he was born, he, along
with two brothers and a sister, was raised by his mother with the
considerable help of her family. Although neither she nor her family
were rich, she commanded sufficient resources to engage governesses
and tutors for her children. When one of these tutors decided to
establish a school for boys, Samuel was sent to it, but the man
proved to be 'quite mad' - touting Samuel in a poster advertising
his school as a boy 'who wrote like the Muses and did other
wonderful things'2 - causing Samuel's mother to withdraw
him from the school. In 1871 he entered Wesley College, which proved
to be an excellent choice for a boy with his talents. Its
headmaster, Martin H. Irving, had been educated at Balliol College,
where Benjamin Jowett had been his tutor; he had emigrated to
Australia to take up a position as Professor of Classical
Comparisons and Philosophical Logic in the University of Melbourne,
a chair he resigned after a few years to accept the position at
Wesley. Wesley College, Alexander later wrote, 'was a very good one,
giving us a broad education in Classics, Mathematics, English (which
was made a point of), French, and some science'. Irving, who was
'rather stern but very kind', set its tone of 'efficiency and
many-sidedness'.3
Irving was the son of Edward Irving (1792-1834), a
Scottish clergyman, who was tried and convicted of heresy in 1830
for preaching that Christ shared a sinful nature with his fellow
men. After his death his teachings were taken up by Henry Drummond
(1851-97) and his circle, and in 1835 this group founded the
Catholic Apostolic Church, whose adherents were known as
'Irvingites'. A chief tenet of this sect was their belief that the
Second Coming was close at hand, and that the church should revert
to its ancient offices of apostles, prophets and evangelists to
prepare itself for this momentous event. Martin Irving himself was a
high official in this sect, but he never tried to convert his
students. When he retired he returned to England to live in an
Irvingite settlement, and visited his old pupil in Manchester.
From Wesley College Alexander went to the University
of Melbourne where his performance was outstanding, but after just
two years and no degree, his mother was persuaded to send him to
England, where it was hoped - indeed, expected - that he would win a
scholarship to either Oxford or Cambridge. He chose to sit the
scholarship examination for Balliol College, Oxford, and was
successful, beating out George Curzon - later Viceroy of India and
Foreign Secretary - who had trained at Eton. Benjamin Jowett, the
Master of Balliol and Regius Professor of Greek, was then in his
prime, and Alexander took his essays to him. Alexander later
recalled that Jowett found his style 'too flowery. The Chinese like
a flowery style. We don't.'4 Alexander must have taken
this criticism to heart, since his mature style can hardly be
described as flowery.
Little is known for certain about the rest of
Alexander's education at Balliol. We know that he studied with A.C.
Bradley, a brother of F.H. Bradley, whose speciality was English
literature. Both T.H. Green and R.L. Nettleship were tutors in
philosophy at Balliol during the years Alexander was a pupil, but no
evidence has come down to us that he wrote papers for either of
them. Of course he may have done so, but our information about his
Oxford education is so sketchy that no stronger statement is
possible.
After gaining his Bachelor of Arts degree, with Firsts
in both Classical Honour Moderations and Greats and Mathematical
Moderations, he decided to try for a fellowship at Oxford, and, for
reasons unknown, he chose Lincoln College, rather than Balliol, for
his attempt. In 1882 he was elected a fellow, a position he was to
hold for the next eleven years. His election made history, for he
was the first Jew to obtain a fellowship at any Oxford college. The
Test Act of 1870 did away with all religious restrictions in higher
education and thus made it possible for dissenters, Roman Catholics
and Jews to matriculate and to be awarded degrees, as well as to
compete for fellowships. The reform legislation did not extend to
women, a flaw that Alexander campaigned to rectify during his years
at Manchester.
The year following his election as a fellow Alexander
spent in Germany where he attended university lectures but did not
work towards a degree. Upon his return he took up an appointment as
a philosophy don in both Lincoln and Oriel Colleges, where he taught
until 1888. During these years he worked on the problems of ethics,
writing a dissertation that was awarded the Green Prize in Moral
Philosophy in 1887. T.H. Green had died in 1882 at the early age of
forty-six and the prize had been established to honour his memory.
During the next couple of years, Alexander turned his dissertation
into a book, Moral Order and Progress: An Analysis of Ethical
Conceptions (1889), which was very well received by the critics
and was reprinted twice during the next several years. When
continued demand led his publisher to propose a fourth impression in
1912, Alexander vetoed the proposal, giving as his reason that the
argument of the book had been superseded by recent developments in
ethical theory.
As its title suggests, Alexander developed an ethical
theory that was firmly based on the theory of evolution, especially
on the doctrine of natural selection. T.H. Green's thoughts on
ethics, first made public in his lectures and then in his book,
Prolegomena to Ethics (1883), edited by A.C. Bradley the year
after Green's death, served as Alexander's starting point. But he
was no slavish follower of Green and firmly but respectfully
criticized his views, rejecting those he found wanting. While
working on it, Alexander worried that his dissent from the master of
fresh and lamented memory would lead his expected audience to
dismiss his book, so he was relieved when F.H. Bradley, who read
proofs for him, voiced no objection to his treatment of Green's
views. Where Alexander departed from Green was in his application of
the idea of natural selection to the sphere of human conduct. Both
Herbert Spencer and Leslie Stephen had attempted something similar,
but Alexander, who had the benefit of their works to draw on,
produced a more fully developed system than either of his
predecessors had done. His ethical theory was very much in tune with
the spirit of the times, and consequently had a wide readership.
Before his book came out, Alexander had taken a leave
from Oxford to live in London. Most of his time there was devoted to
private study, but he did teach a course in elementary psychology at
Toynbee Hall and he presided over its philosophical society. One of
the principal aims of Toynbee Hall, the Universities' settlement in
East London founded in 1884, was to provide educational
opportunities for London's poor. In its early years, many recent
graduates of Cambridge and Oxford put in a few years teaching under
the auspices of Toynbee Hall before taking on permanent employment.
At that time it was considered fashionable to teach there. Not
surprisingly, Alexander found his pupils too ill-prepared to absorb
what he had to teach them. They had a long way to go before they
would reach the level of his Oxford undergraduates.
His work on ethical theory had led him to study both
biology and psychology, and he continued to read in these subjects
in London. C. Lloyd Morgan (1852-1936), who was then just beginning
to develop his theory of emergent evolution, gave Alexander's book a
very favourable review, which led to a life-long friendship between
the two men. The doctrine of emergence plays a central role in
Alexander's later metaphysical work. Alexander also became
fascinated with recent developments in experimental psychology - at
that time not taught at all in England - and in 1890-91 he went to
Germany to work in the psychological laboratory of Hugo Münsterberg
at Freiberg. When he returned to Oxford in 1891 he offered a course
of lectures in psychology in each of the next two years, and while
he was professor at Manchester, he recruited T.H. Pear (1886-1972)
to inaugurate a course of study in experimental psychology.
Upon his return, Alexander continued to feel
dissatisfied with his Oxford post, so he decided to apply for vacant
professorships. Despite strong letters from many prominent
intellectual figures, including Bernard Bosanquet, A.C. Bradley,
F.H. Bradley, Benjamin Jowett, Gilbert Murray, Leslie Stephen and J.
Cook Wilson, he was unsuccessful in his first three applications.
Given the times, religious prejudice may have been a factor, but
there is no way of knowing whether it was or not. On his fourth
attempt, in 1893, he was elected Professor of Philosophy in Owens
College, later to be transformed into the University of Manchester,
and he taught there until his retirement in 1924. The budget at
Manchester allowed him an assistant and in the course of his tenure
he gave a number of men, who later gained prominence, a start in the
profession. Alexander was an outstanding teacher, and he devoted
much of his energy to that task. In his reading he continued to
prepare himself for writing what would be his magnum opus, Space,
Time, and Deity, which was not published until 1920.
Space, Time, and Deity is an extraordinary work
of synthesis. There are elements in it of neo-Hegelianism, the new
realism, Bergsonianism, Kantianism, relativity theory, emergent
evolution and experimental psychology. Little wonder then that its
gestation took so many years. Indeed, the book might never have been
written at all if the University of Glasgow had not invited
Alexander to deliver two sets of Gifford Lectures while the First
World War was raging. Once he had committed himself, the necessity
to deliver forced him to formulate the thoughts suggested by his
wide reading into a system. Over the years he had published a number
of articles which gave his readers hints of the direction of his
thinking, but they were only hints and the full scope of his system
did not become public until after he had delivered his lectures.
Alexander's book was one of the last attempts by a
British philosopher to advance a fully developed speculative
world-view. Only two of his contemporaries, John McTaggart Ellis
McTaggart (1866-1925) and Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947), were
later to publish competing systems. McTaggart's The Nature of
Existence (1921, 1927) took its inspiration from Hegel, but
followed its own path, especially in its treatment of time.
Whitehead's Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (1929)
arose out of a background very similar to that of Alexander's book.
Indeed, when Whitehead's book was announced Alexander, according to
Dorothy Emmet, 'thought that his work would be superseded by
Whitehead's. He remarked that he could say, as Dr. Johnson said of
himself with regard to Burke, that he had "rung the bell" for
him.'5 When Alexander read Whitehead's work, he realized
that they had very different approaches to the problems of
metaphysics. Whitehead, he thought, had taken a Leibnizian path,
whereas he had followed Spinoza. Their different approaches, plus
Whitehead's bewildering neologisms and his unusual uses of ordinary
terms, make comparison of the two systems nearly impossible. Thus
Alexander's book stands quite alone in the history of
twentieth-century philosophy.
Alexander was not a philosopher who sought disciples,
nor would he have been happy had acolytes come and asked to sit at
his feet. Almost certainly, he would have said something designed to
shock them out of their intellectual servitude. In a letter to Susan
Stebbing in 1930 Alexander put the matter this way: 'The fact is I
believe I am rather provocative than anything else; and I've made up
my mind that my business is to make people think, even if their
reflections condemn me. I'm very deficient in soundness and
thoroughness. And you know what W. James said, that any fool can be
original.'6 Alexander's provocative speech was never
uncivil, and few, if any, ever felt offended by anything he said. In
his speech at the unveiling of the Epstein bust he remarked: 'though
I shall be glad if it is said of me "He was known for a certain
gaiety of speech," I prefer to have it said of me, "He contrived for
some years to persuade people that he could think." For, my Lord, in
spite of appearances to the contrary, I am really and truly and
fundamentally a very serious man; it is only that I find it
difficult to be dull.'7 Very, very few people can make
such a claim about themselves. In the same speech, he attempted to
account for the great affection shown him during his lifetime: 'I
cannot tell how I have won this affection; unless it be that I
possess a fair stock of affection myself, which extends to all
children and to dogs and cats and other animals. Apart from that,
after careful self- examination, I can only conclude that there must
be something in me which in the 18th century they used to call a
je ne sais quoi.'8 Those of us who never had the
pleasure of meeting Alexander cannot comprehend this mysterious
quality to which he refers, but we can read the works he wrote and
in that way share in the fruits of an intellect bold enough to set
down a systematic account of everything there is or ever will be.
John G. Slater University of Toronto, 2000
NOTES
1 The British Journal of Psychology, vol. 17
(1926-7), pp. 305-21. 2 Quoted in 'Memoir' by John Laird in
Philosophical and Literary Pieces by Samuel Alexander
(London: Macmillan, 1939), p. 2. 3 Laird, op. cit., p. 2.
4 Laird, op. cit., p. 6. 5 'Foreword to the 1966
Reprint Edition' by Dorothy Emmet in volume 1 of Space, Time, and
Deity (New York: Dover Publications, 1966), p. xvii. 6
Laird, op. cit., p. 73n. 7 Laird, op. cit., p. 73.
8 Laird, op. cit., p. 72.
Introduction to Collected Works of Samuel
Alexander (Thoemmes Press, 2000) volume 1, pp.v-xi,
Introduction
© John Slater, 2000.
|