The Conclusion of the Critique of pure
reason1
It is well known that the fundamental problem of
Kant's Critique of pure reason is that of the possibility of metaphysics
as science. It is the issue raised by the guiding question of the book: how are
synthetic a priori judgments possible? What is much less known and
infinitely less evident, is Kant's answer to this cardinal problem whose urgency
he so well signified. How is metaphysics actually viable according to Kant?
Where does Kant answer in a clear and distinct fashion the question concerning
the grounds for synthetic a priori judgments?
The uncertainty that
bears on this matter can certainly account for the diversity of interpretations
that have been suggested of Kant's solution to the dilemma of metaphysics. I
will single out four major trends in the Kant literature. For some, Kant
appeared mostly as the philosopher who wanted to liquidate metaphysics
altogether as he defied metaphysicians to justify the validity claim of their
so-called science. This iconoclastic reading has endured ever since Mendelssohn
coined the phrase about the "alles zermalmenden" Kant, that is Kant as
the rebell who wanted to do away with two millennia of metaphysics. This reading
is maintained, to quote one of its most recent instances, by the russian
interpret Arsenij Gulyga, who writes: "In fact, Kant never gave an answer to his
question at the beginning of the Critique, «how is metaphysics as science
possible?» His transcendental dialectic destroyed all dogmatic claims in this
sphere"2
. According to a second line of interpretation, Kant did jettison classical
metaphysics, but he replaced it by something like a theory of science, one which
would reflect solely on the principles at the root of scientific knowledge or,
more generally, of our perception of reality or what has been dubbed our
"conceptual framework". One could speak here, following Paton's
quasi-paradoxical formulation, of a "metaphysics of experience". A third reading
of Kant's solution took its departure from Kant's famous passage where he
confessed he had to suppress knowledge to make way for faith, a metaphysical
faith based on the ressources of pure practical reason. Kant's moral philosophy
would thus be the new form of metaphysics. This reading has been suggested by
Gerhard Krüger and more recently, albeit in a different vein, by Manfred
Riedel3.
Finally, there have been interpretations suggesting that Kant actually wanted to
save the tenets of aristotelian-leibnizian metaphysics, that laid claim to a
knowledge that surpasses the shallow dimension of experience. This has been
called the metaphysical interpretation of Kant.
So many, often
conflicting, interpretations have not come about randomly. They certainly have
something to do with the fact that Kant never seems to give a concluding
response to the issue of the possibility of metaphysics and its synthetic a
priori judgments. In clear, there is no text in the first Critique
that would spell out in a straightforward manner: here is how the problem of
metaphysics is to be solved, here is how synthetic a priori judgments by
pure reason are possible. One does not find, in short, a "conclusion" to Kant's
Critique of pure reason, or, what is more customary in his writings, some
kind of Schlussbemerkung, where Kant would make a summary of his research
and condense his answer to the inaugural question of his work so well stated in
its masterly Introduction.
Nevertheless, such a response, such a
"conclusion", must be found somewhere in the Critique of pure reason,
since it is precisely to solve the problem of the possibility of metaphysics
that the first Critique has been written in the first place. Instituted
as a propedeutics to metaphysics, the Critique has no other goal than to
sort out the possibility of synthetic a priori cognitions. Its raison
d'être consists in establishing the credibility of some form of rational
metaphysics. Kant writes very specifically in the Introduction: "It is upon this
inquiry, which should be entitled not a doctrine, but only a transcendental
critique, that we are now engaged. Its purpose is not to extend knowledge, but
only to correct it and to supply a touchstone of the value, or lack of value, of
all knowledge a priori. Such a critique is therefore a preparation so far
as may be possible, for an organon; and should this turn out not to be possible,
then at least for a canon of pure reason, according to which, in due course, the
complete system of the philosophy of pure reason (...) might be carried into
execution"4.
The complete system of pure reason, which Kant announces in this context under
the heading of a "transcendental philosophy", is what should come after
the transcendental critique which is the Critique of pure reason,
understood as the propedeutic destined to deliver the touchstone for a system of
metaphysics. "Such a system might be called", says Kant in the conditional
tense, "a transcendental philosophy". But, he cautions: "that is still at this
stage too large an undertaking"5.
It is too much, because one does not yet know how such a metaphysical or
transcendental knowledge is possible. Thus the necessity, Kant argues, of a
propedeutic to transcendental philosophy, that is of a "transcendental critique"
that would lay the groundwork for a transcendental philosophy" or a metaphysics,
that has yet to be developped. - Today, one often understands under
"transcendental philosophy" a reflection on the "conditions of possibility" of
this or that. For Kant this type of reflection belongs specially to a
transcendental critique. For a transcendental philosophy, as Kant understands
it, the question of its "conditions of possibility" has, in principle, already
been resolved.
The transcendental critique of 1781 thus aims at the
clarification of the legitimate metaphysical use of pure reason to make way for
the establishment of a metaphysics. The preface to the second edition will
therefore define the critique as a "treatise of method", as a Traktat von der
Methode, which, Kant insists, is "not yet a system of science itself"6
– as metaphysics or transcendental philosophy promises to be. The
Critique thus recommends itself as an attempt (Versuch), "to
change the procedure (Verfahren) adopted hitherto in metaphysics,
accomplishing in it a total revolution"7.
In itself, the project of a transcendental critique that would function as
prolegomena to any future metaphysics is of a remarkable transparence. What is
less clear meanwhile, is its realization, its solution, its conclusion, in one
word, the exact meaning of the transformation that has to be carried through in
the method extolled thus far in metaphysics. What is the meaning of this new
method of pure reason?
Our search for this "conclusion" of the
Critique has to start with Kant's initial formulation of the problem: how
are synthetic a priori judgments possible? As we all know, this problem
is subdivided, for the Critique of 1781 as for the Prolegomena of
1783, into three sub-questions: how are synthetic a priori judgments
possible 1. in pure mathematics, 2. in pure physics and 3. in metaphysics. This
threefold question can also espouse the following form: how are pure
mathematics, physics and metaphysics possible? In the presentation of the
Prolegomena, which in this respect corresponds fairly well to the
architecture of the Critique, the first question is delt with in the
transcendental Aesthetic, the second in the Analytic, the third in the
Dialectic. As as matter of fact, the Aesthetic does account for the possibility
of pure synthetic cognition in mathematics by relying on the mediating instance
of the pure intuition of space and time, in which the synthetic a priori
assertions of mathematics can be construed and verified, because pure time and
space allow for some sort of ideal illustration. In a much more complex
argument, that we cannot analyse here8,
the Analytic attempts to justify the synthetic a priori cognitions of
pure physics by appealing to the "third term" of "possible experience". As for
the Dialectic, it is, to be sure, concerned with the genuinely metaphysical
pretensions of pure reason. But the case of the Dialectic is somewhat particular
insofar as it doesn't reach, as was the case in the Aesthetic and the Analytic,
a really positive result, i.e. a solution to the problem of the legitimacy of
metaphysics as science. Kant admits it unabatedly, and in many ways. First of
all, when he divides his transcendental Logic in an Analytic and a Dialectic, he
unmistakingly specifies that the former offers a Logic of truth and the second a
"Logic of illusion". Does that entail that metaphysics can only be illusory? Is
the realm of the a priori knowable limited to pure mathematics and
physics? Furthermore, Kant often concedes that the task of his Dialectic is for
all intents and purposes merely negative, since it deals with the world of
illusion or Schein 9.
Does
one have to conclude that metaphysics is then unredeemable? This would most
certainly be the case if the Dialectic was the last word, or the last section,
of the Critique of pure reason. But it isn't. After the Dialectic comes a
Methodology (Methodenlehre). I would now like to argue that this
transcendental theory of method, far from being a mere appendix to the
Critique, as it is often thought to be, represents the genuine outcome of
Kant's critical undertaking. It serves, so to speak, as the positive counterpart
to the Dialectic, as the arena where one has to find Kant's original solution to
the problem of metaphysics. Without this positive outcome, the question of the
possibility of synthetic a priori judgments remains without any
answer.
One must first recall that the Methodology represents the second
major section of the Critique, as a whole, after the transcendental
theory of elements (that contains the Aesthetic and the Logic, Analytic and
Dialectic). This is not meaningless. The inaugural division of Kant's
transcendental critique is that between a theory of elements and a theory of
method. If the Methodology has the honor of being the last section of the book,
it is because the very idea of a theory of method is intimately linked to the
original project of a Critique of pure reason. The Critique
defined itself, we remember, as a "treatise on method" that aims at a
fundamental revolution in metaphysics by exposing the corner stone of
metaphysical cognitions. In its very conception, the Critique of pure
reason has no other task than to revolutionize metaphysics by proposing a
new methodology that could lay the foundations for a rigorous metaphysics. It
then seems appropriate to learn anew to see in the methodology the logical
outcome of Kant's critical investigation. By exagerating only slightly, one
could claim that the transcendental theory of elements had no other object than
to sort out the elements of pure reason. The original import of the Critique
could then be found in its methodology. What is undoubtable is that the
institution of a new metaphysics did not take place anywhere in the
transcendental theory of elements.
Kant defines the transcendental theory
of method as the "determination of the formal conditions of a complete system of
pure reason"10,
which has yet to be developped under the title of a metaphysics. It aims at
clarifying the conditions for the legitimate use of pure reason with view to
this metaphysics. The Critique of pure reason doesn't have a more urgent
task. After defining its purpose, Kant lays out the plan of his methodology:
"Toward this end [i.e. the determination of the formal conditions for a complete
system of pure reason] we will deal with a discipline, a canon, an architectonic
and finally a history of pure reason"11.
After going through the Dialectic, one can easily grasp why the Methodology will
open on a discipline of pure reason. Since metaphysical reason naturally
falls pray to transcendental illusion, a pure reason keen on its proper method
needs a discipline before anything alse, that is an instruction with a negative
purpose, following Kant's own expression12.
To this extent the discipline can be said to duplicate the therapeutical and
critical effort, in the negative meaning of the word, of the Dialectic. It is
not in this Discipline that one will find a positive answer to the inquiry on
the possibility of metaphysics.
It is only in its second act, in the
Canon of pure reason, that the Methodology will draw out the new foundations of
metaphysics. The idea of a "canon" of pure reason had already been broached in
the Introduction of the Critique, at one of its most strategic junctures,
where the project of Kant's Critique was in the process of defining
itself. Let's quote again the relevant portion of the text: "such a critique is
therefore a preparation... for a canon of a priori cognitions, according
to which... the complete system of the philosophy of pure reason might someday
be presented"13.
Where should we find this "canon" of the legitimate use of pure reason, the
avowed goal of the first Critique, if not in its Canon of pure
reason?
Kant offers a general, but limpid definition of what is to be
understood under a canon: "I understand by canon the whole (Inbegriff) of
the a priori principles of the legitimate use of certain faculties of
knowledge"14.
If this faculty of knowledge is pure reason itself, as is here the case, its
Canon will necessarily indicate the a priori principles of the legimate
use of pure reason. This earmarking associates in striking fashion the Canon to
the original purpose of a critique of pure reason. Does the Critique have
a more precise objective than the sorting out of the a priori principles
of the correct employment of pure reason?
Yet did we not learn from the
Dialectic that it is vain to expect any kind of metaphysical knowledge? Did it
not consign all the possibilities of the sophistic arguments of metaphysics "in
the archives of human reason in order to prevent similar errors in the
future"15?
Certainly, but Kant now says that this failure only concerns pure theoretical or
speculative reason, the reason that rests solely on the syllogisms of pure
reason to obtain a priori knowledge. This failure of theorerical reason
is inexorable and Kant insists that there can be absolutely no canon for this
reason, but only a negative discipline16.
If there is a canon of pure reason at all, it will only deal with the practical
use of reason, which Kant introduces here as an entirely new outcome that he is
setting out to explore: "Consequently, if there be any correct employment of
pure reason, in which case there must be a canon of this reason, the canon will
not deal with the speculative, but merely with the practical employment, which
we shall now proceed to investigate"17.
This passage makes quite clear that if there shall be a legitimate use of pure
reason, there must be a canon for it. The determination of the justified
employment of pure reason, goal of the Critique, has to be found in its
canon.
Kant immediately underscores the urgency of his inquiry by giving
the first section of the Canon the title: "On the ultimate end of the pure
employment of reason". Without any doubt, one is also reaching the final end,
the culmination point of the entire Critique of Pure reason that will
link the possibility of metaphysics to the practical interest of pure reason.
Kant's argumentation starts with a recollection of the three objects of reason
as they emerged from the Dialectic: the freedom of the will, the immortality of
the soul and the existence of God18.
All those objects are of the utmost interest to us, says Kant, but that
interest is not really of theoretical nature19.
By that he means that those objects, could they be known, would be of no utility
"in concreto, that is in the study of nature"20.
The interest we attach to those ideas, Kant contends, is genuinely practical.
And "practical means that which is possible through freedom"21.
Kant's argument is that there are conditions of freedom that are not only of an
empirical import (if not, moral philosophy would amount to a mere empirical
anthropology). There are also moral laws that originally belong to reason and
that compell us in an unconditional and universal manner. There is thus an
"efficiency" of pure reason that is not of theoretical nature and about which a
canon will be possible. Kant writes: "Pure practical laws, whose end is given
through reason completely a priori, and which are prescribed to us not in
an empirically conditionned, but in an absolute manner, would be products of
pure reason. Such are moral laws and these alone, therefore, belong to
the practical employment of pure reason, and allow of a canon"22
The
practical interest we associate to the three ideas of reason, towards which "all
the preparations of reason are oriented in the realm of what one can call pure
philosophy", only wants to sort out "what is to be done, if our will is free, if
there is a God and a future life"23.
Claiming here that practical freedom can be confirmed by experience, a thesis
that is far from constant in Kant, and that it belongs as such to speculative
philosophy, Kant limits, as early as the first Critique, the scope of his
canon of pure practical reason, to two objects: "we have therefore in a canon of
pure reason to deal with only two questions, which relate to the practical
interest of pure reason, and in regard to which a canon of its employment must
be possible: Is there a God? Is there a future life?"24.
The practical, if not existential object of the Canon is concisely
circumscribed.
It also echoes Kant's basic concern in his inquiry on the
possibility of metaphysics. The metaphysics that Kant looks for in the
Critique does not aim at the establishment of a scholastic system that
would produce a priori definitions of all concepts through the run down
of a caracteristica universalis. Kant's metaphysics is an "interested"
metaphysics from the outset. It hopes to answer the original metaphysical
preoccupations of man, the questions that constitute what Kant calls the
metaphysica naturalis, that has always existed and that will always
continue to exist as a natural disposition. Its essential qualms are the
existence of God and the immortality of the soul. Can this metaphysics ever
acquire scientific status? Can there be a rigorous science regarding the most
elementary metaphysical aspirations of man, which can never be content, Kant
writes, with that which is merely temporal25?
This metaphysical thirst can be condensated in the twofold question: is there a
God? is there a future life?
Even if those questions concern more closely
what Kant calls the practical use of reason, one must nevertheless never lose
sight of the theoretical ambition of Kant's inquiry on practical reason in the
first Critique. Kant is indeed still looking for the touchstone of a
metaphysics. Kant readily acknowledges it at the very beginning of the Canon:
"however (indessen) there must be some source of positive cognitions
(einen Quell von positiven Erkenntnissen) that belong to the domain of
pure reason, but that only give occasion to error solely owing to
misunderstanding, while yet in actual fact they form the goal of reason's
zeal"26.
Even if Kant is only discussing the practical employment of reason, one will
nonetheless discover in this usage the source (Quell) or the touchstone
for positive cognitions in a metaphysics out of pure reason. It is this
foundation or touchstone that the Critique of pure reason has to put into
light in order to edify a metaphysics. The road that leads to a metaphysical
cognition, whose synthetic a priori claim would be legitimate, passes
through the study of the principles of pure practical reason. This, I submit, is
the sense of the methodological revolution Kant attempts to carry through in the
method hitherto observed in metaphysics.
The "ultimate end of the pure
employment of reason" (title of the first section) has now been determined. It
lies in the question: is there a God and a future life? It will be up to the
second section of the Canon to explain more precisely in what this new method of
practical reason consists, the only one still open to rational metaphysics. It
is entitled: "On the Ideal of the highest good as a determining ground of the
ultimate end of pure reason". Its first paragraph sums up the path of reason
throughout the transcendental Dialectic. Reason has led us to speculative ideas,
but those ideas have redirected us toward experience in a certainly useful
manner, but which nonetheless doesn't correspond to our expectations27.
In other words, the result of the Dialectic is quite honorable, but it didn't
really satisfy our expectations since it left unresolved the question of the
possibility of metaphysics, thus failing to answer the most vital questions of
reason, regarding God and the immortality of the soul. It is at this strategic
juncture that the perspective of a practical metaphysics will begin to unfold:
"Only one more attempt remains to be undertaken: to see whether pure reason may
not also be met in the practical sphere, and whether it may not there conduct us
to ideas which reach the highest ends of pure reason that we have just stated
and whether, therefore, reason may not be able to supply to us from the
standpoint of its practical interest what it altogether refuses to supply in
respect of its speculative interest"28.
At this decisive step of the argument where he alludes to the interest of
reason, Kant puts forward the three famous questions that express this interest
of reason: what can I know? what should I do? what may I hope for? The first
question is only speculative (bloss spekulativ), Kant contends. He prides
himself of having exhausted all possible answers to this question in his
Critique, but, then again, "we remain as far away from the two great ends
towards which all the effort of pure reason strives"29
- the two great ends coined in the question "is there a God? is there a future
life". Kant then goes on to set aside rather swiftly the second question that
expresses the interest of reason: what should I do? Resorting to almost the same
terms he used to diminish the urgency of the first question, he declares: "the
second question is only practical (bloss praktisch). As such, it doesn't
belong to the scope of pure reason. It is not a transcendental, but a moral
matter, that doesn't have to concern our Critique". The second question
(what should I do?) is thus provisionally discarded from the discussion of the
"ground for the determination of the ultimate end of reason" in the
Canon.
Kant's entire attention will be devoted to the third question: "if
I do what I ought to, what may I hope for?" This question, he says, has the
advantage of being both practical and theoretical, since hope invests every
action we undertake, but it is also theoretical, then what is hoped for or hoped
"in" entails a certain kind of cognition, that has yet to be circumscribed. What
evidently appeals to Kant, is that the practical here serves as a kind of a
relay to the theoretical concerns of reason, in such a way that "the practical
can lead as a guiding thread to the solution of the theoretical question"30.
What Kant here envisions is, without any doubt, a solution to the theoretical
question through the practical use of pure reason.
The text of the Canon
stresses quite clearly this passage from the practical to the theoretical: "I
maintain that just as the moral principles are necessary according to reason, in
its practical employment, it is in the view of reason, in the field of
its theoretical employment, no less necessary to assume that everyone has
ground to hope for happiness in the measure in which he has rendered himself by
his conduct worthy of it"31.
One can find in this relaying of theoretical reason through practical reason the
main thrust of Kant's solution to the possibility of metaphysics. It is in
itself revealing that the entire second section of the Canon will only deal with
the third question concerning the interest of reason, the question of hope. It
contains the key to Kant's initial problem.
What does hope strive for?
Kant answers, in the simplest of terms: "all hope strives towards
happiness"32.
Realistically or pessimistically, Kant believes however that our quest for
happiness will never be fully satisfied under empirical conditions (and who
could claim that he is wrong?). The supreme happiness that everyone is striving
for is not one which could be realized in our terrestrial existence. It is
appropriate, I think, to translate the word Glückseligkeit employed here
by Kant through something like a "happiness of felicity", a Glück of the
Seligen. What our reason truly hopes for is not a greater enjoyment or a
merely material well-being, but a peace of soul that is not only of this world.
To be sure, we cannot generate this felicity, this Glückseligkeit, by
ourselves. The only thing we can do, and hope for, is to make us worthy of such
a happiness of felicity.
By this means, Kant does give an answer to the
question "what ought I do?" that he claimed to avert in his transcendental
enquiry: "you ought to do what will make you worthy of happiness"33.
And to make oneself worthy of happiness is to act, as much as we can, according
to the spirit of the moral law provided by pure practical reason. The ultimate
intent of our hope can therefore only consist for pure reason in the allocation
of such an eternal happiness that would be proportional to the morality of our
actions (or our maxims of action). Such a hope only makes sense, clearly, if one
admits the existence of a supreme intelligence that is capable of securing this
"necessary link between the hope for happiness and the unremitting effort to
make oneself worthy of happiness"34.
It is this link between the hope of reason and its accomplishment that
constitutes the ideal of the highest good in the first Critique35.
One easily recognizes here the well-known doctrine of the postulates of
practical reason that crowns the second Critique. The essential tenets of
this doctrine can already be found however in the Critique of 1781, where
they form its proper conclusion.
It is to be noted that Kant's
perspective in 1781 differs on a crucial point from the doctrine presented in
1788. Whereas the Critique of practical reason will consider the respect
for the moral law, unter complete disregard from any future reward, as the sole
legitimate motive of morality, the Canon of 1781 still sees in the promise of a
future felicity a necessary mobile of moral action. Much less rigorous than the
second Critique, the Critique of pure reason sides more closely
with classical ethics: "Thus without a God and without a world invisible to us
now, but hoped for, the glorious ideas of morality are indeed objects of
approval and admiration, but not motives (Triebfedern) of purpose and
action because they don't fulfil in its completeness that end which is natural
to every rational being and which is determined a priori; and rendered
necessary by that same pure reason"36.
The first Critique openly espouses a "system of morality that rewards
itself"37,
ein System der sich selbst lohnenden Moralität. This system contends that
the supposition of a wise world ruler is a "practical necessity" in order to
"give moral laws their effectivity"38.
Reason, Kant claims in 1781, is compelled "either to admit such a being and with
it a life in a world that we have to consider as future, or to regard moral laws
as vain hallucinations (leere Hirngespinste)"39.
We
can now comprehend to what extent the highest good, understood in the
perspective of 1781, can provide a positive answer to the twofold query of pure
reason: is there a God? is there a future life? A positive answer is defensible,
Kant argues, since they are necessary conditions to ensure the coherence of the
system of morality. From here we can fully grasp the meaning of the title of the
second section of the Canon: "The ideal of the highest good as a determining
principle for the ultimate end of reason". The hope rendered possible by the
principle of the highest good enables us to ground on the basis of pure
practical reason what Kant insistingly calls the "two cardinal propositions of
our pure reason: there is a God, there is a future life"40.
This is, in the Critique of pure reason, the clearest of answers to the
fundamental problem of metaphysics.
But, one might ask, have those two
cardinal propositions really been "founded"? The propositions "there is a God,
there is a future life" are evidently synthetic a priori judgments, that
theoretical reason failed time and again to prove in the Dialectic. How can we
justify such claims before the tribunal of a transcendental critique? We know
that a mediating third term is necessary in order to account for the legitimacy
of any synthetic a priori judgment. What is this tertium quid in
the case of the postulates of practical reason? The first Critique, as
far as we can see, does not squarely address this matter, content, as it is,
with laying out the programme of a future metaphysics based on the reality of
practical reason. On can find an answer to this question in the second
Critique, where Kant writes: "In order to extend pure knowledge
practically, an a priori purpose must be given, i.e., an end as an object
(of the will) which, independently of all theoretical principles, is thought of
as practically necessary through a categorical imperative directly determining
the will. In this case, the object is the highest good"41.
What here authorizes the a priori extension of knowledge in a practical
horizon, is a purpose, an Absicht, an a priori interest of reason,
linked to its cardinal thirst: is there a God? is there a future life? The
possibility of what Kant labels, ackwardly enough, pure practical knowledge lies
in the underlying purpose of the highest good.
Now, is it legitimate to
conclude from a purpose to the reality of its object? Is man immortal simply
because he happens to desire it? Is God's existence proven because it appears to
be a necessary piece in the realization of the highest good conceived by reason?
Does the philosopher who constantly warned us throughout the Dialectic not to
take our metaphysical desires for realities fall prey to a similar illusion?
Kant did not confront this objection in his Critique of 1781, but he did
in an important footnote to the second Critique. Kant there refers to an
argument raised by Wizenmann against the doctrine of the highest good. Wizenmann
"disputes the right to argue from a need to the objective reality of the object
of the need, and he illustrates his point by the example of a man in love, who
has fooled himself with an idea of beauty which is merely a chimera of his own
brain and who now tries to argue that such an object really exists
somewhere"42.
Wizenmann clearly aims at Kant's practical metaphysics adumbrated in the Canon
of the first Critique, which he must have read very well. Kant agrees
with Wizenmann as far as mere contingent or empirical desires are concerned: "I
concede that he is right in all cases where the need is based on inclination,
which cannot postulate the existence of its object even for him who is beset by
it, and which even less contains a demand valid for everyone, and which is
therefore a merely subjective ground of wishes"43.
From the desire to the reality of what is desired, the consequence is not
cogent. But the purpose that leads us to postulate the existence of God and the
immortality of the soul is not, Kant suggests, an inclination like any other
else. We are not preoccupied here with a random subjective inclination, that
would be particular and empirical, but with a Vernunftbedürfnis,"with a
need of reason arising from an objective determining ground of the will, i.e.,
the moral law, which is necessarily binding on every rational being; this,
therefore, justifies a priori the presupposition of suitable conditions
in nature and makes them inseparable from the complete practical use of reason".
In Kant's mind, the pure interest of reason is objective for it is universally
shared by all rational beings, deriving from the only positive a priori
of pure reason, the moral law that compells unconditionally. This unconditional
command of reason has as its goal, its telos, the highest good. To jettison this
universal aim of the moral law, would be tantamount to robbing reason of any
efficiency and, ultimately, of any coherence. Why would reason enjoin us moral
beings to seek the realization of an impossible ideal? To acquiesce to moral law
as the principle of moral action entails that we assume at the same time its
aim, the highest good and the two conditions of its actuality, that is the
existence of God and the immortality of the soul. The objectivity of the
postulates of practical reason stems from the unquestionable objectivity of
moral law and the rationality it opens up to human existence. One has to see in
this conclusion, in this logic of practical rationality, the real conclusion of
Kant's Critique of pure reason, whose purpose was to appreciate the
legitimate employment of pure reason with view to the establishment of a
rigorous metaphysics.
This conclusion should not lead to any triumphalism
of pure reason. The practical postulate of God's existence and of the
immortality of the soul is the only positive content of a metaphysics based on
the logic of practical hope. By paraphrasing a passage of the Paralogisms, one
could say that the proposition "there is a God, there is a future life"
constitutes the "only text" of Kant's practical metaphysics. But this conclusion
will only appear modest to the rationalist schools who nurtured much higher
ambitions in their pursuit of a priori knowledge. Nonetheless Kant feels
that it suffices if one wants to answer - and philosophy has no other purpose -
the questions raised by the interests of reason and entertained by every mortal.
This will be the concluding words of Kant's Canon of pure reason and,
consequently, of the first Critique: "But, it will be said, is this all
that pure reason achieves in opening up prospects beyond the limits of
experience? Nothing more than two articles of belief? Surely, the common
understanding could have achieved as much, without appealing to philosophers for
counsel in the matter". But, Kant counters, "do you really require that a mode
of knowledge which concerns all men should transcend the common understanding,
and should only be revealed to you by philosophers?"44
Kant's metaphysics of the interests of reason doesn't want to transcend the
scope of common sense, but to serve it and to justify the claims of its faith.
Herein lies the consequence, and the novelty perhaps, of Kant's reorientation of
metaphysics towards the requirements of practical reason, that serves as the
bed-rock of his "cosmical" understanding of philosophy as the "science of the
relation of all knowledge to the essential ends of human reason"45.
This philosophy, Kant concludes, does not "advance further than is possible
under the guidance which nature has bestowed even upon the most ordinary
understanding"46.
Those are the concluding words of Kant's Canon.
It is now time for our
own reflection to conclude. The purpose of our enquiry was not to "invent" a
conclusion for a book that doesn't have one in its table of contents. The issue
of the conclusion of the Critique of pure reason that we wanted to call
to attention is not a matter of literary composition, but a fundamental concern
of any reader of Kant's first Critique. What is at stake is the true
nature of Kant's answer to the possibility of metaphysics. The metaphysics Kant
is aiming at would, if it is ever possible, offer an answer to the most
essential, the most interested questions of pure reason: is there a God? is
there a future life? It is to sort out the grounds for such an answer that Kant
institutes a Critique of pure reason, designed as prolegomena to any
future metaphysics. When he wrote his first Critique, Kant had no idea
that he would go on to write two other Critiques. This means that in the
perspective of 1781, the one we maintained throughout our argument, one
Critique will be enough to yield the groundwork of metaphysics. As a
treatise on method, the Critique indeed indicated a new path to future
metaphysics. As early as 1781, this path is that of pure practical reason,
effective and credible through its imperative command and in the coherence of
its system of morality, that culminates in the ideal of the highest good. From
the vantage point of this "principle", Kant will effectively attempt to answer
the main problems of the metaphysica naturalis. It is then the Canon that
solves the question of the possibility of metaphysics. This finds confirmation
in the rather dramatic diction set forth in the Canon ("if there is any
legitimate employment of reason, there must be a canon", also
evident in its titles: "On the ultimate end of the pure use of reason", "On the
ideal of the highest good as a determining ground for the ultimate end of
reason", etc.). After this Canon, Kant will proceed to spell out an
Architectonic and a History of pure reason, the last two sections of the
Critique. They will indeed lay out in an extraordinarily sketchy fashion
the plan for the system of metaphysics that the Canon has just made possible.
One could thus consider those two ultimate chapters as an appendix to Kant's
Critique of pure reason and its conclusion, the Canon of pure
reason.
1 This text was presented at a meeting of the North American Kant
Society in New Orleans on April 26, 1990 and published in the Graduate
Faculty Philosophy Journal 16 (1992), 165-178. A lengthier French version of
it appeared in the Kant-Studien, 81, 1990, 129-144. We thank the
Kant-Studien for their permission to publish a shortened
translation.
2 A. Gulyga, Immanuel
Kant, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1985, p. 152.
3 G. Krüger, Philosophie und Moral in der kantischen Kritik,
Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1931, 2. Aufl. 1967. M. Riedel, Urteilskraft und
Vernunft. Kants ursprüngliche Fragestellung, Frankfurt am Main :
Suhrkamp Verlag, 1989.
4 B 26; transl.:
Critique of pure reason, transl. by N. Kemp Smith, New York: St. Martin's
Press, 1965, p. 59
5 B 25, transl., p.
59.
6 BXXII; transl., p.
59
7 Ibid.
8 See chapter III of our
inquiry Kant et le problème de la philosophie: l'a priori, Paris:
Vrin, 1989
9 Compare A 63-4/B
88.
10 A 707-8/ B 735-6;
transl., p. 573.
11 A 708/ B
736.
12 A 709/B
737.
13 B 26.
14 A 796/B
824
15 A 704/B
732
16 A 796/B
825
17 A 796-7/B 824-5;
transl., p. 630 (modified).
18 A 798/B
826
19 Ibid.
20 Ibid.
21 A
800/B828
22 A 800/B 828;
transl., p. 639.
23 Ibid.
24 A 803/B 831; transl,
p. 634.
25 B
XXXIII.
26 A 795-6/B 823-4;
transl., p. 629 (modified).
27 A 804/B
832.
28 Ibid; transl., p.
635 (modified).
29 A 805/B
833.
30 A 805/B
833.
31 A 809/B 837;
transl., p. 638.
32 A 805/B 833;
transl., p. 636.
33 A 809/B
837.
34 A 810/B
838.
35 See A 810/B 838:
"Ich nenne die Idee einer solchen Intelligenz, in welcher der moralisch
vollkommenste Wille, mit der höchsten Seligkeit verbunden, die Ursache aller
Glückseligkeit in der Welt ist, so fern sie mit der Sittlichkeit (als der
Würdigkeit, glücklich zu sein) in genauem Verhältnisse steht, das Ideal des
höchsten Guts".
36 A 813/B 841;
transl. p. 640.
37 A 809/B
837.
38 A 818/B
846.
39 A 811/B B
839.
40 A 741/B
769.
41 Kritik der
praktischen Vernunft, Ak. V, 134; transl. Immanuel Kant, Critique of
practical Reason And Other Writings in Moral Philosophy, transl. by L. W.
Beck, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949 (repr. : New York and
London: Garland Publishing, 1976), p. 236.
42 Ibid. Ak. V,
143-4 (English translation, p. 245).
43
Ibid.
44 A 830-1/B
858-9; transl. p. 651.
45 A 839/B 867;
transl., p. 657.
46 A 831/B
859.