Commentary
on Heidegger's Being and Time
by Chris Morrissey (c) 1997 More C
Communications Inc.
From the Internet's Heidegger list
(June 9-10, 1997)
Heidegger in a nutshell
The representational character of 'truth' is only a
privitive and
derived formulation; self-conscious acts begin the slide
away from
primodial being and into a privitive form of being. The
most authentic
mode of being for Dasein is some sort of unconsicous but
assured and
skillful care and concern of the environment and others.
Exactly. Heidegger sets the stage
for this thesis in Sections 1-4. Let us briefly recap the truly radical
movement of these sections to see how he does so. I insert my observations
under the headings of "Commentary":
Section 1
"The Necessity of Explicitly
Restating the Question of Being"
Thesis: In metaphysics, "a
dogma has been developed" about the question of Being.
Question: Why does this dogma have
to be deconstructed in _Being and Time_?
Answers:
(a) Aristotle's "unity of
analogy" is the best (non-)explanation the tradition has for the
"universality" of Being. But what this "unity of analogy"
means is totally obscure. The tradition has not made the insight of ancient
ontology (which peaked with Aristotle) any clearer.
(b) The "indefinability"
of Being is not an answer to the question of Being. It only shows that Being is
not a being. The tradition is oblivous to this distinction, which Heidegger
will name the "ontological difference."
(c) The "self-evidence"
of Being in cognition and assertoric language is, in fact, an a priori enigma.
We may say, "The sky is blue" and self-evidently know what
"is" means. But the very fact of this everyday self-evidence is no
answer to the question of *why* this fact should in fact be the case.
Conclusion:
To deconstruct the metaphysical
dogma about Being exemplified in these three doctrines
("universality," "indefinability," and
"self-evidence"), the question of Being needs to assume a new form.
Commentary:
Heidegger announces his rejection
of traditional ontology. At the very beginning of _Being and Time_ he announces
his intent negatively, i.e. his intent is *not* to refute the traditional
answers to the question of Being. That is, he does not engage the tradition
here and there in order to dispute the adequacies of its arguments. Instead, he
intends to ask the question of Being in a new way and, in so doing, to show
indirectly that the traditional answers are in fact inadequate because the
question of Being heretofore has been inadequate. Positively, he hopes to attain
results from his new question; but, even if he does not (as in fact he was
unable to, since he never finished _Being and Time_), the power and radicality
of the new question itself will be enough positive demonstration of the
tradition's shortcomings.
Heidegger's announced method is
therefore oneupmanship, viz., the tradition will be shown to have the wrong
answers because it will be shown to have asked the wrong questions. Heidegger's
fatal error here is that he assumes in advance that, because he poses the
question properly, the answer to this new questioning of Being must necessarily
be, not only different from, but incompatible with the indications of
traditional ontology. But cannot two different questions point to the same
answer? Why must Heidegger decide in advance that his new question will yield
an answer that necessarily sets him in opposition to the tradition's answers?
For, in fact, Heidegger's new
questioning never yields results or answers, and only professes to open up a
new realm of questioning. So why then does the overcoming of metaphysics
(through this new questioning which supercedes all old questioning) necessitate
the destruction of metaphysics (i.e. the rejection of all traditional answers
as obstacles)? The answer here seems to be that Heidegger sees the
"answers" of the tradition as stumbling blocks to thought, in that
they predetermine the [allegedly] impoverished form of questioning preserved by
the tradition.
His method, therefore, is to clear
these stumbling blocks out of the way before setting out on a new path that
asks the new question. Otherwise the wrong answers will continually invite the
wrong questions. However, in so doing, he has set limits to the possible
answers his new questioning may yield. This is because, in clearing the path,
he has put the old stones in another, predetermined place. However this does
not mean that Heidegger has made covert assumptions of which he is unaware, as
if he has closed off a particular path by carelessly throwing the old stones in
front of that path. Rather, he is very explicitly aware of where he has
consigned the old stones. The attentive reader can track, in the subsequent
sections in which the new path is charted, the way Heidegger consciously
decides to displace these traditional stones. The careless reader will
uncritically accept Heidegger's move beyond the tradition and remain unaware of
what is questionable in Heidegger's own motion.
Section 2
"The Formal Structure of the
Question of Being"
Thesis: The question of Being must
be circular, because one who *is* asks about the Being in any thing which *is*.
Argument: The fact of our
pre-understanding of Being has not been adequately recognized by the tradition.
When this fact is forgotten, the question of Being cannot be asked properly,
because the pre-understanding of Being remains unquestioned. There is no
escaping the necessary circularity of the question, because we already are *in
fact* within the circle. The form of the question of Being must therefore take
the form of this circle. We must enter the circularity of the question and
attempt to uncover our pre-understanding of Being. The question of Being takes
its circular form from the structure of the a priori of Being.
Commentary:
The question of Being, according to
Heidegger, must address the factual a priori pre-understanding we have of
Being. This is a more radical attempt to think Being than the tradition,
because it will attempt to think this factual a priori in a way the tradition
[allegedly] has not, i.e. with reference to an a priori we always already
possess. The radicality of the new question justifies itself, according to
Heidegger; the more radical the question is, the more philosophical it is. This
may be true; but what is not addressed by Heidegger is why there is nothing
other than the factual a priori that is ultimately worthy of thought. He raises
the factual a priori to preeminence and exhorts entry into the circle of
questioning which its preeminence necessitates. But he has no inkling of
anything that could outwit this circle of questioning and stand outside its
circular grasp. Heidegger consciously decides from the outset that philosophy
can either move along the straight line of its ontological logic, or it can,
more radically, move along the circle of questioning of the a priori of Being.
Heidegger consciously decides to exclude from philosophy any access outside
this circle to other dimensions and figures. He sets strict limits to how the
question of Being can be posed.
Objection:
I'm not sure if you are agreeing or disagreeing with this,
Chris. There is
no specific disagreement listed, but you "sound"
as if you are not
particularly settled with H.s approach. H. does make room
for standing
outside the circle through the derivitive notion of
explanation. But he also
makes sure we all know that explanation has its weaknesses.
Do you have an
issue with the circularity of this hermaneutics?
Response:
Agreeing or disagreeing outright
would be superficial. But there are problems with this approach.
Because if ontical phenomena are
derived *only* from metaphysics, and metaphysics is derived *only* from the
pre-understanding of Being, then Da-sein is indeed locked in the philosophical
circle that Heidegger draws. For this entails that the question of Being
circles through the ontological (i.e. the framing of the Being of beings) and
the ontical (i.e. the factical ground of this framing which is open to Being
Itself) for all time. The questioning of Being moves through the circle: now
giving ontological priority to Being, now giving ontical priority to Being; now
questioning Being in beings, now questioning Being in Da-sein.
Yet it is only because Heidegger
has partitioned *in advance* the proper functions for philosophy and the ontical
sciences that he can be locked in this circle. It is worth questioning whether
this demarcation of realms is fatal or not. For perhaps theology is more than
an ontical science (cf. _Being and Time_, section 3), with more than faith
(defined solely as Da-sein's Being-toward-God) as an "object."
Moreover, perhaps something more than the a priori of Being determines what is
or is not derivative for Da-sein, revealing Heidegger's geometry of
hermeneutics as rashly impoverished.
Section 3
"The Ontological Priority of
the Question of Being"
Thesis: All ontology, although it
makes all ontical science possible, has been oblivious of the pre-understanding
of Being.
Argument: Ontical sciences rely
upon ontology to disclose the Being of the beings they investigate. For
example, a concept of life makes biology possible. This is the priority of
ontological questioning to ontical science, viz., the questioning about the
Being of beings. Such questioning has priority because it makes the ontical
sciences investigating these beings possible. But ontology itself, while making
such decisions about the Being of beings, has not yet addressed Being Itself.
This is a significant omission; for, as decisions about the Being of beings
make ontical sciences possible, the decision regarding Being Itself has made
ontology itself possible. Heidegger claims to initiate new question of Being,
i.e. the inquiry into Being Itself.
Commentary:
Notice that here Heidegger makes
theology an ontical science. Here he has consciously decided to move the
stumbling stones of the tradition to a spot which makes entrance to his new
path possible. The inattentive reader will miss this and merely be seduced by
the novelty and power of Heidegger's questioning. Yet it should never be
forgotten that this novelty and power is possible only because he has
consciously decided against the position of the old stones. He provides no
argument for moving aside the old stones; he will only point to the novelty and
power of the new path.
So what has Heidegger lost by deciding
to make theology an ontical science? He loses any kind of place for faith in
philosophy. Faith becomes a merely ontical phenomenon that can have nothing to
say about ontology. If it does say something, it can [allegedly] only do so by
fixing beforehand the Being of beings in a particular way and, in so doing,
close off any possible inquiry into Being Itself. Faith is [allegedly] capable
only of an ontology that identifies Being Itself with God. Thus faith can only
ensnare thought in a metaphysical way of thinking about Being and has no
resources to think Being Itself.
Therefore Heidegger decides in
advance that philosophical questioning has ontological priority over faith when
it comes to questioning Being. This is a fatal error, because, on the one hand,
he assumes in advance that philosophy alone has, as its sole function, the
founding of ontical sciences. Thus he has pre-decided that philosophy has
nothing to say about how to live one's life. On the other hand, because
theology alone (or "faith," which he has decided should be its sole
object) has no jurisdiction in deciding about Being and in opening ontical and
factical realms, it must be subordinate to the decisions of philosophy.
"Faith" may tell you how to live, but this [allegedly] can have nothing
in common with thinking Being.
So Heidegger has decided beforehand
that faith must be disentangled from philosophy, otherwise there can be no
progress in the question of Being. Just as Luther smashes dogma to give faith
priority in its realm (i.e. ontic experience), Heidegger smashes dogma to give
philosophy priority in its realm (i.e. ontological decisions). Note that the
characteristic of such smashing is that reason is separated from revelation
through the establishment of jurisdictions. Jerusalem has nothing to do with
Athens. The Bible has nothing to do with Aristotle, says Luther. Christian
philosophy is a square circle, says Heidegger. The difficulty with this
decision is that, while it purports to be just, i.e. to give each its due (its
rightful jurisdiction), it omits the possibility that faith is more than an
ontic phenomenon ("man's being towards God") but factical
manifestation of something that is beyond all facticity and beyond all a priori
conditioning of that facticity. Faith which surpasses all understanding can
outwit, not only beings, but Being Itself. (cf. Jean-Luc Marion, _God Without
Being_)
And thus a philosophy not open to
faith can only see as far as the ontological difference; and, for that matter,
only that far after having carved out the jurisdictions of philosophy and
science with the ontological difference. The questioning of faith is not
consigned to the fate of decisions about the Being of beings or even Being
Itself.
Section 4
"The Ontical Priority of the
Question of Being"
Thesis: The pre-understanding of
Being, which is decisive for all ontology (which in turn founds the ontical
sciences), must be analyzed as the circular ontico-ontological existence
(Da-Sein) that it in fact is.
Argument: Just as ontologies found
ontical sciences, so too must there be a fundamental ontology that founds all
ontologies. This fundamental ontology can be uncovered if the pre-understanding
of Being which is characteristic of human Da-Sein can be analyzed. (Heidegger
will later abandon the project of fundamental ontology - i.e. the project of
_Being and Time_ - in order to enter more deeply into the path of the circular
questioning of Being.) Da-Sein is the name for the being who has its own pre-understanding
of Being. The existence named Da-Sein is both "existential" and
"existentiell": The former term, i.e. "existential," refers
to the fact that Da-Sein lives metaphysically, i.e. must construct ontologies
which in turn make possible ontical fields of experience. The latter term, i.e.
"existentiell," refers to the factical ground which alone is capable
of exhibiting to an analysis the original pre-understanding of Being. Both
terms together describe the unitary, circular ontico-ontological existence that
is Da-Sein.
Commentary:
In section 3, because he established that, in questioning Being,
ontology has priority over the ontical sciences (because it questions beings in
their Being), Heidegger swung from ontical beings to the ontological question
of Being. Now, in section 4, he swings back to the ontical; not, however, to
ontical beings, but to the ontical manifestation of that peculiar being for
whom Being is a question. This ontical manifestation is different from other
ontical beings insofar as it is absorbed in the circular movement of both a
factical (i.e. peculiarly ontical) pre-understanding of Being and an
ontological founding of the Being of beings.
Having declared, in section 2, that
only an entrance into the circular questioning of Being can uncover the issue
of the pre-understanding of Being, Heidegger comes full circle here. He moved
through the ontological priority in section 3 and now circumscribes the ontical
priority in section 4. Having declared the ontological decisions of philosophy
to rule over all ontical phenomena, he now moves back to factical life for the
ontical-existentiell ground of all ontological-existential decisions.
Heidegger makes clear his contempt
for Aristotle and Aquinas on the soul. This is strange, because nothing he
cites from them is incompatible with his new questioning of Being thus far. He
does not justify his charge against them of "a vapid subjectivizing of
beings." He merely takes the opportunity to set himself in opposition to
them in no uncertain terms. What follows in _Being and Time_ must, in its
exhibition, show why he is opposed to them.
The careful reader must therefore
decide whether what follows in _Being and Time_ is in fact the "genuine
ontological structure" of Da-Sein by comparing it with the work of
Aristotle and Aquinas. The careless reader will assume that Heidegger has
merely superceded these thinkers and will shrink from the labour which
Heidegger shirked. Heidegger moves on in _Being and Time_ to demonstrate the
novelty and power of outquestioning the tradition. What remains for the reader,
then, is to engage the tradition in questioning, instead of simply trying to
outquestion it.
The price Heidegger pays for this
outquestioning, viz., the separation of ethics from philosophy (because [allegedly]
only the decisions of philosophy about Being can make ethics possible), may be
too high. In outquestioning metaphysics, the question of Being may have closed
itself off from the "genuine ontological structure" of Da-Sein,
especially if Da-Sein is more than the circular ontico-ontological phenomenon
adumbrated in _Being and Time_. Faith claims that Da-Sein is more than this;
but Heidegger cannot think on this, since he has made a decision about faith in
advance.
A preliminary exchange on Section 5
well, i am already unclear and heid. seems to be asserting
things
that are not established, to my recollection. i.e., re the
very
first sentence in this section: how did we "show"
that we must
pinpoint and ascertain some correct access to a primary
being?
i know heid's been suggesting that we must and that da-sein
is
the being we must examine (in-it-self). but when did we
'show' that we 'must' do that?
Heidegger showed this in section 2.
The argument was: Because the
question of Being must be circular (i.e. we
can't stand outside of Being and
ask about it), we need access to a primary
being (i.e. the best one available
for circular questioning). The primary
being has both an (ontological)
understanding of Being and pre-ontological
(ontical) understanding of Being.
That's Da-sein, a.k.a. Mr. Circular.
be-that-as-it-may, onward: if we are going to examine
da-sein,
it makes sense that a) [page 14] da-sein is most closely
related to: the "world" BUT heid writes in later
marginalia:
"*ie, here in terms of what is objectively
present" DOES this
mean that the present-at-hand is indicated here as most
closely related to da-sein (as in the next sentence:
"ontologically reflected back upon the interpretation
of da-sein.")
No, "present-at-hand" is
not the most closely related to Da-sein. In the
ontological moment of Da-sein's
ontico-ontological structure, the answer to
your question is yes. But ontology
and representation and technical
thinking, as you know, are not all
there is to Da-sein. There's more to
factical Da-sein than the
present-at-hand.
and it appears that heid hedges all of this with a
provocative
sentence (last sent. in last full paragraph on p 14:
"Only when
the fundamental structures of da-sein are adequately worked
out with explicit orientation toward the problem of being
will
the previous results of the interpretation of da-sein
receive
their existential justification.
How is that a hedge? Instead,
Heidegger is being thorough.
The "fundamental
structures" elucidate Da-sein in all his gory facticity.
Doing this in the light of the
question of Being means making this an
ontico-ontological elucidation, so
that the full circle of the question of
Being is moved through. Not just
*ontical* facticity, but also
*ontological*, i.e. existential,
Da-sein. If you move through the whole
circle, as Heidegger will in _Being
and Time_, you get the
ontological-existential as well as
the ontical-existentiell.