TEN THESES ABOUT PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AND THEORY OF EXPERIENCE

Beppe Pavoletti (Acqui Terme - Italy)

December 1st, 1996

[ frames ] [ no frames ]


ABSTRACT

The essay argues in favour of the reality of phenomenological consciousness, not to be conceived as an inner theatre, but rather as a being-in-the world. Observations about ontology, reductionism, role of language.


CONTENTS: THE TEN THESES

1.   PHENOMAL CONSCIOUSNESS DOES EXIST (so eliminativism is false)

2.   NATURE OF CONSCIOUSNESS ENTAILS THE FACT THAT IT IS ONTOLOGICALLY SUBJECTIVE

3.   FROM THE REALITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS FOLLOWS THAT WORLD DOES EXIST AT LEAST AS AN APPEARANCE

4.   CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT AN INNER EYE THAT SEES MENTAL EVENTS SUCH AS EXPERIENCES, PAINS, FEELINGS (there is no Cartesian theatre)

5.   CONSCIOUSNESS AND SELF ARE NOT OBJECTIFIABLE AND CONSCIOUS STATES ARE NOT THINGS OR OBJECTS

6.   CONSCIOUSNESS IS NEITHER A COLLECTION OF DISCRETE EVENTS NOR A DESERT LANDSCAPE: IT COULD BE BETTER DESCRIBED AS A STRUCTURED MULTIDIMENSIONAL FLOW

7.   SUCH PROBLEMS AS OTHER MINDS OR IDENTIFICATION OF ONE'S OWN EXPERIENCES ARE FACTUAL, NOT GRAMMATICAL OR A PRIORI

8.   LANGAUGE IS NOT INDEPENDENT FROM CONSCIOUSNESS, AND IT'S JUST A RELATIVELY SMALL PART OF EXPERIENCE

9.   CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT SEPARATE FROM THE WORLD

10.  EMPIRICAL WORLD AND CONSCIOUS STATES CAN'T BE IMMEDIATELY CONFLATED

 


Following theses deal with several controversial points of today's debate about consciousness, although they in several forms have been object of investigation in the past history of philosophy.

For the sake of clarity, I have exposed my thoughts in form of theses about philosophy of mind and theory of experience. My thoughts were influenced, among others, by Searle for the issue about subjectivity and by DeWitt for the distinction between the metaphysical and the semantic issue about realism. Furthermore I was influenced by Berkeley and by Schopenhauer as to the theory if experience and the subject-object relation, by Heidegger for the "being in the world", by Descartes and by Dennett for his criticism to the "Cartesian theatre" (although my theses are about opposite to most Dennett’s theories), by Kant and others. Also the recent book "The conscious mind" by David J. Chalmers contains many interesting insights. Furthermore, for some important observations, I'm in debt with my friend Mark Adkins (Arizona State University).

My theses are just a starting point, and leave several question to further investigation. I hope that they can help someone to develop his/her own thoughts, and to philosophize better than me.

I'll be glad to get comments about them.


TEN THESES ABOUT PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AND THEORY OF EXPERIENCE

1. PHENOMAL CONSCIOUSNESS DOES EXIST (so eliminativism is false)

As was pointed out, among others, by Searle in "The rediscovery of the mind" and by Chalmers in "The conscious mind" such claim needs no proof: if one is not conscious there is no way to show him that consciousness exists, and if one is conscious, consciousness shows itself to him, it's not something to be searched (Aristotle said that one should be able to see what needs proof and what doesn't). This thesis should be seen as a commitment to neither idealism nor realism: such issues need further investigations. In other words, phenomenal consciousness is matter of direct experience, not a theoretical concept. It seems that among the features of eliminativism there is taking phenomenal consciousness as a theoretical concept put forth to explain behaviour and social interaction; thus, one might argue that if we might conceive alternative ways to explain such phenomena, we can get rid of consciousness. This argument in itself is valid: simply, consciousness is not a theoretical concept ... Of course, another possibility is that eliminativists are actually zombies, that have no direct experience of consciousness. But at this point we shouldn't make the mistake to take consciousness as an object of experience: knowing that consciousness exists is a matter of direct experience, but object of experience are things we see, hear, smell and so on, not consciousness itself (more on this in following points). I'm also wondering if eliminativism is even inconsistent, because it admit the existence of entities such as persons, object around us and so on: but such entities are in turn characterized by features that I can't understand but as taken from conscious experience, that is as having such and such an appearance, such and such a form and so on. And form, appearance and other similar features are derived from phenomenology we have access to in conscious experience. However, this shows a weak point of eliminativism, but I'm not sure it's enough to show that it is also self-contradictory.

From the thesis (1) follows an interesting conclusion related to debate about strong AI: if strong AI wants to reproduce intelligent behaviour or computational processes that are supposed to happen in the brain (or even that are just accepted as a reconstruction of human reasoning processes, as an as-if explanation, no matter how correspondent to real one), such aim might be successful, but it has as such nothing to do with subjective consciousness: it simply deals with something else so far as I know this idea doesn’t appear very often in the literature; for example it is endorsed in one of the few Italian books about philosophy of mind, "L'enigma della mente" (Mind's enigma) by Sergio Moravia; the more general thesis that describing and explaining neurophysiological or computational processes is not describing and explaining phenomenal consciousness is largely dealt with in Chalmers' work; one could conceive the purpose of strong AI as reproducing subjective consciousness by means of artifacts, but this looks more as a (very interesting) technical than as a philosophical problem: however my theses doesn't entail any commitment to that. But about the last point it is important to note that here I mean reproduce subjective consciousness as I described it in thesis (1) and in following ones, that is with its subjectivity, that is not the same as saying that subjective consciousness is what is reproduced by strong AI.

One might wonder what is the place of consciousness within a scientific world's view. The first thing I've to say here, is that I see no reason to commit to the thesis that today's science provides an absolute, definitive world's view. Rather, I think that there are several ways of investigating the world, and that science itself is subject to transformations, so that we can't reliably foresee which science we'll have, say, in the year 2150. However, it is clear that today's physics and biology have not theories adequate to cope with consciousness. At this point we have two choices: 1. admit that there is something falling outside of the scope of science 2. admit that we need more wide and powerful scientific theories in order to cope with consciousness

I think that these two choices are ultimately the same thing: they simply means that we need other theories than ones of today's science. Had we such theories, we could say that science has grown enough, with new theories, to embrace a domain wider than before, or that a new discipline has been developed outside the field of science. Such distinction (as the one between science and metaphysics) are not meaningless and not useless, but should be taken with care because beyond a certain point they tend to become mere labels. After all, ancient philosophers didn’t care very much about such differences because what they really care about was understanding the world.

2. NATURE OF CONSCIOUSNESS ENTAILS THE FACT THAT IT IS ONTOLOGICALLY SUBJECTIVE

This thesis doesn't means that reality of consciousness is subjective in being a mere opinion, but that subjectivity is its own way of being, as real as the objective way of being of physical objects (if they exist outside of consciousness). Hence follows that we need a non-reductionist ontology, that be able to cope with several way of being and with their mutual relations. I think that Thomas Nagel, in "A view from nowhere", has clearly pointed out such need, and maybe Chalmers in "The conscious mind" has pointed out it even better: in the world there is something beside physical events and processes. In the history of philosophy such non-reductionist ontologies have already been attempted: for example, Aristotle's thesis of "analogia entis"; this an example of a pluralistic ontology. Other ontologies are non-reductionist in the sense that they don't conflate reality with material reality: think for example to idealistic metaphysics. It is also worth noting that an idealist as Hegel didn't think that physical objects are immediately to be taken as mental, but that the Idea has several ways of being and of manifesting itself. And we might also think to Spinoza and many others. Generally speaking, I think that strong dualism and idealism may have their own flaws, but are nevertheless more plausible than eliminativism.

3. FROM THE REALITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS FOLLOWS THAT WORLD DOES EXIST AT LEAST AS AN APPEARANCE

Note that at this point I'm committed with neither metaphysical realism nor with metaphysical idealism, so I don't mean "appearance" as the opposite of "reality", but only as "what appears, what is manifest" (phenomenon). Thus the world is not lost, nor turned into a mere social and linguistic product (society and language are nothing but a part of the world, with no privileged position): it exists, tough it might turn out that it's not just appearance, but "mere appearance", as claim phenomenalists. Debate about realism as existence of knowledge-independent beings, and about correspondence truth has almost nothing to do with this thesis: in fact what is claimed here is the existence of the appearance. This thesis is compatible with the claim that world exists as a mere appearance. The claim that world exist in some other way which transcends appearance is not the only alternative: one could argue that appearance are appearing things, appearing beings, without put things and beings absolutely beyond appearance. At this point, one might be tempted to think that we are here dealing with sense data, but I don't think: the expression "sense data" is far from clear, but it seems that it is mostly intended as referring to raw feelings, pure experience without no conceptualization, no self-awareness, maybe no self at all. I agree that such sense data are a kind of myth, unless we take them non as a reality, but just as a concept useful to analyze our experience (ens rationis cum fundamento in re). All the same, we must admit that something is given, that there is a direct access to the being, that entities we have primary access to are not epistemic and semantic ones (say concepts, statements, beliefs, interpretation, utterances and so on). This means that we must admit that the so called myth of the given is non just a myth, provided that we speak of the given in the context of a theory of a consciousness like the one I'm trying to put forth, and not a pure, abstract given (calling something a myth is not an argument, but I suspect that there are more reasons to speak of the myth of the language than of the myth of the given)

4. CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT AN INNER EYE THAT SEES MENTAL EVENTS SUCH AS EXPERIENCES, PAINS, FEELINGS (there is no Cartesian theatre)

The most dangerous mistake one can make at this point is to think that consciousness is a sort of inner eye that allows us to know our thoughts, pains and so on, in the sense that all these states would be the object of such eye. But such an eye would be simply a duplication of the real consciousness: instead of saying that I am seeing a thing, I say that my mind is seeing the image or the representation of a thing. But to explain that I need in turn another mind in the mind that see the image of the image, and so on. This is the well known argument of Dennett against what it calls "Cartesian theatre"; this arguments appears in several Dennett’s works, such as "Consciousness Explained". I agree with it, but not with most of other Dennett’s theories. BTW, I found the argument not only in Dennett, but in "Cognition and reality" by Ulrich Neisser, published in 1976; similar claims can be found in some works of the Thomists, and Schopenhauer, from an idealist point of view, follows the same path in saying that object and subject are mutually relative. Other interesting observations about the matter are to be found in the note 34 to the last chapter of Putnam's "Pragmatism: an open question" (that note sounds strangely realist, and the whole work looks as intended to criticize more relativism than realism). Thus, saying that statements about objective reality are inferences from our mental states looks as obvious only from the point of view of the inner eye: in fact, someone (typically a direct realist) could argue that as there is no inner eye what we perceive are not our perceptions, but real things. It goes without saying that the expression "Cartesian theatre" is assumed as a manner of speaking, but I'm far from sure that the very core of Descartes' thought has been such and implausible view; rather I suspect that if he live today, he would agree with views endorsed by Searle, Chalmers and myself.

5. CONSCIOUSNESS AND SELF ARE NOT OBJECTIFIABLE AND CONSCIOUS STATES ARE NOT THINGS OR OBJECTS

This thesis follows immediately from (4) and (2). Of course, I'm not saying that mental states don't exist, but only that they don't exist as things or as objects. I FEEL a pain, but I HAVE a chair. This is maybe the very interesting thing we can learn from the so called private language argument: according to one of possible interpretations the deepest Wittgenstein's insight was not a behaviourist one, and not even a language-related one, but was that of the subjectivity of the mental. However, I tend always to say in the PLA a behaviourist and eliminativist position. But here it is most important to point out that consciousness and conscious states are not the object of experience: they are rather to be seen as a transcendental level, consciousness being the horizon that makes possible experiencing something as an object. The fact that consciousness is a matter of experience without being itself object of experience has also been very properly called transparency of consciousness, and is quite a puzzling feature

6. CONSCIOUSNESS IS NEITHER A COLLECTION OF DISCRETE EVENTS NOR A DESERT LANDSCAPE: IT COULD BE BETTER DESCRIBED AS A STRUCTURED MULTIDIMENSIONAL FLOW

Characters of consciousness are both variety and non-discreteness, as follows from (5). In many of today's philosophy of mind we read only of beliefs, desires and simplest non-propositional states, such as headache. But non-propositional states are far more complex and interesting: indeed, they are maybe the most interesting aspect of consciousness, or at least among the ones that make life more interesting: let's think to sensations, perception, feelings, mood (very well dealt with in Searle's "The rediscovery of the mind"), and to more complex states, such as being in love (it's a pity that love has received so few consideration from philosophical analysis). But let's go somewhat deeper in analyzing the structure of conscious experience. I think that we can recognize three levels: * small scale structure * large scale structure * metastructures The small scale structure is experience seen at the level of such elementary entities as sounds, colours and so on: seeing red here and now, for example. The large scale structure is the experience of the world: the red I'm seeing here and now is actually a red car that is in a certain place that I can locate in space and time as a part of a world extended beyond experience I've here and now access to. The metastructures are higher level elements revealed by means of the seeing-as: for example see a certain material object, which such and such dimensions, as a gothic cathedral, a set of sounds as a musical composition (and, even more, as a symphony of Beethoven rather than as an opera of Verdi) and so on. It goes without saying that the three structures are not three entities assembled together to constitute experience.

7. SUCH PROBLEMS AS OTHER MINDS OR IDENTIFICATION OF ONE'S OWN EXPERIENCES ARE FACTUAL, NOT GRAMMATICAL OR A PRIORI

What is real is also possible: thus, consciousness that is real for me is not in principle impossible for other beings similar to me, and not even for dissimilar ones. It is a matter of the fact whether such beings are actually conscious: it has nothing to do with features of the language we use to speak about mental states (the starting point is the beetle in my own box, not the supposed ones in the boxes of other people: if in my box there is a such and such thing, it could be present also in other ones). In a similar way we deal with the identification of experiences: no doubt that one can be wrong in classifying his own experiences; for examples, he can believe he has already seen something he sees for the first time. Again, it is a matter of fact whether he's right or wrong. Experience and life are somewhat puzzling, confusing and dramatic, but we can't escape from such features by taking refuge in the regularity of grammar.

8. LANGAUGE IS NOT INDEPENDENT FROM CONSCIOUSNESS, AND IT'S JUST A RELATIVELY SMALL PART OF EXPERIENCE

Language is a particular event and activity within the experience, it is not and absolute starting point, and even less a substitute for the world, as some extremely language-oriented philosophers seem to think. Of course, I'm not denying in any way that the study of language is a very important and interesting one. BTW, I'm not sure that the very distinctive feature of analytic philosophy is the exclusive orientation towards language: such orientation has been criticized by some philosophers that are more or less growth within the analytic tradition, such as DeWitt, Hawking and others, for example Michele Marsonet, an Italian philosopher who has worked very much in USA (and one can cite other philosophers that surely are not German metaphysicians, for example Russell, Ayer and Mundle). Maybe analytic philosophy is more a style than a content. But this is not the most important point. What is important, is the claim that language is not independent from mind and consciousness, although mind-language relations are not simple to deal with. But we can try to go deeper into this issue, for example to explain meaning. I tend to think that meaning might be conceived as a transactional process involving linguistic symbols such as sound and signs and conscious language user: in this perspective, meaning is not a separate entity whose relation to concrete, material utterances e should discover, but rather is a process within the category of the seeing-as, a metastructure (see thesis 6). Thus meaning is not a thing, but rather the process of seeing something as meaningful, according to certain physical features and to other elements such as interpreter expectation, social praxis and so on (I'm not giving here a full theory of language). It is worth noting that in such perspective the interpreter is not the creator of the meaning, because meaning exists primarily from the point of view of the speaker. This conception is speaker-centered, as opposed to interpreter- centered theories, like the one of Davidson, where the speaker becomes a mere sounds/signs producing device, and about the whole job is carried out by the interpreter. I think that with such theories there is behaviourism lurking in the background, because their conception of the speaker seems quite behaviourist (it is unclear, for me at least, whether the interpreter should be in turn seen in a similar behaviourist view.

9. CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT SEPARATE FROM THE WORLD

World is not a show being played on the stage of my own consciousness: indeed, consciousness is consciousness of being in the world (remember Heidegger's in-der-Welt-sein). I'm conscious as a part of a world. Kant's warnings about the need of holding at the same time the empirical realism and the transcendental idealism means that I am an empirical being just as things in the world around me, so such things are not simply representation of mine as a particular empirical being. Nevertheless, the whole point is puzzling; for example, it is worth noting that world appears as my experience and at the same time I experience my existence as existence as a part of the world.

10.EMPIRICAL WORLD AND CONSCIOUS STATES CAN'T BE IMMEDIATELY CONFLATED

This thesis follows from (4), (5) and (9), and means that the fact that I'm conscious of a car doesn't entail that car is nothing but a conscious state. Notice the "immediately": this thesis holds for the phenomenalist just as for the realist. It means that there is a distinction between the empirical world (the so called 'external world') and one's mental events, no matter how we interpret the external world (mere appearance or thing in itself). Thus "tree" refers to trees in the empirical world, and "my thought of trees" refers to my thoughts of trees, that are quite other things; even if both trees and thoughts were mere appearances, they would be structurally different ones. In sum, at a certain level - that of everyday life, social life and even science (maybe within certain limits) - we can act as empirical realist, even if we are transcendental idealist, that is we can deal with world as if it was an external, objective one, even if it were not. The place of realism and idealism is at an higher level of abstraction.